Archives de catégorie : Non classé

Destruction of Speech

DESTRUCTION OF SPEECH

The argumentative forms of rebuttal are based on what is said, that is, on a critical examination of the content of the rejected speech, of its relevance to the current issue, or on considerations related to the person who holds it. Good or bad, the refutations are explicitly argued.
Argumentative discourse, like any discourse, can be attacked, either by such an argued refutative discourse or by more radical, linguistic or non-linguistic coups. Speech destruction seeks to impair, nullify, exclude, the targeted speech; to make nonsense of what it says, to render it devoid of substance; to make it repulsive — and, above all, to make it harmless, to ensure that it will have no practical effect on the group.

1. Discourse destruction and freedom of expression

In view of their material exclusion from the public sphere, controversial beliefs and proposals can be neutralized by the legal prohibition of their expression, and the imprisonment of their proponents. This can be seen as an attack on freedom of expression; but many democratic countries agree to legislate against hate speech as an incitement to crime.
Freedom of expression can also be hampered by popular demonstrations, where public expression is made inaudible, by shouting, blowing horns, etc.

2. Destruction by interactional behavior

In ordinary face-to-face situations, discourse can be destroyed by nonverbal interactional maneuvers, the most radical of which is the refusal to listen, and let others listen to the discourse of others. Agreement, which is manifested through various phenomena of ratification, and, conversely, a simple lack of ratification, the inertia of the partner, can cause the speaker to withdraw her speech, S. Disagreement.

The following interaction takes place in a high school physics lab. The lesson is on the concept of force, and uses a small apparatus, a stone hanging from a gallows.[1] The students work in pairs, and we’ll follow students F and G. The question asked by the teacher is:

What are the objects acting on the stone?

The two students look at the teacher in confusion. Then, still addressing the class, she adds:

Well, I took an object in the most general sense that is to say, anything that can act on the stone er: visibly or invisibly if – well\

Then, Student F immediately answers the teacher’s question, by turning to his partner:

Well the air/ the air/ … the air it acts the air when you do that the air\

After a pause, F resumes his argumentation, by vigorously waving his arm up – down – up, while intensely addressing his partner (simplified transcription):

If you do that there will be air afterwards because you know when you make a fast movement like that\ it’s the same there’s the air\ I’m sure\ but here for now we don’t answer that yet but/

Then student G, playing with the stone, says:

There is attraction\

F‘s argument is perfectly in line with Toulmin’s model of argument. The claim is “the air [acts on the rock]”. It is supported by an appeal to analogy, “it is the same”, which refers to an ad hoc gesture of argumentation, that mimics and emphasizes some self-evident fact. The conclusion is duly emphatically modalized, “I am sure » — and immediately withdrawn: “but for now we are not answering that yet”. In view of the strongly asserted argument, this withdrawal is quite unexpected. It is understandable only in view of the interactional behavior of the interlocutor partner G, who stares at the stone and gives no sign of ratification throughout, not even signaling that he is listening to F‘s argument.
This attitude should not be interpreted as contempt for his partner, with whom he gets along very well, as the following fully collaborative exchange shows.

3. Rejecting the expression

An embarrassing discourse can be destroyed by a criticism that focuses upon the style and expression of the opponent without considering the argument itself. The response “I don’t agree” actually demonstrates a high level of cooperation.
Ancient rhetoric identifies a trio of major linguistic qualities of discourse, quality of language, clarity and vividness of expression (latinitas, perspicuitas and ornatus respectively). Destructive strategies can develop from each of these points.

3.1 Quality of Language

You are hardly understandable, you don’t even know the language you pretend to speak, you use dialect expressions you should try to speak classical Syldavian”. In a polemical situation, the opponent may reject a discourse a priori on the basis of its grammatical errors. It would be wrong to think that these strategies are marginal or ineffective:

In an uncertain spelling, Mrs. X challenges the evaluation of her linguistic skills by the jury of the competition.

Ms. X failed her language proficiency test. Now, she disputes the jury’s decision, and the jury responds by mentioning the “uncertain spelling” in her complaint letter. Strictly speaking, these misspellings do not prove that her exam paper was also misspelled, but they can certainly be used as an indication. In any case it justifies a charge of negligence, which shows a disregard for the jury, which is sufficient to devalue the importance of her complaint.

3.2 Clarity and vividness of expression

Similarly, devastating strategies appeal to the lack of clarity of expression: “the presentation was unclear and confusing”, or its vividness “so boring!”.

Of course, it is  better for an argumentative speech to be grammatically correct, clear and interesting. On the other hand, it is human nature to consider correct, clear, and interesting the those speeches with which we agree. This is not just a psychological or bad faith issue; it has a cognitive relevance. The discourse with which one agrees is better known; its deep principles are fully accepted, it is easier to recover the ellipses and missing links; its variations are better tolerated; it is better memorized, etc. When it comes to an opponent’s discourse, it is relatively natural to translate the corresponding difficulties as speech defects, and to conclude by denying that the minimum conditions for mutual understanding are met.

Making fun and puns out of the opponent’s discourse, is a popular way to get rid of the problems and arguments defended S. Laughter and Seriousness; Orientation Reversal

4. Ignoring the argumentative details

A class of refutative maneuvers refers to the opponent’s discourse without considering its argumentative details, e.g.:

— Declaring the discourse sub-argumentative, unworthy of a refutation, S. Dismissal.
— Misrepresenting the argument, S. Resumption of speech.

5. Disqualifying the Arguer

Personal attacks against the speaker set aside the argument and try to disqualify the arguer.

For other forms on the verge of destruction and propositional refutation, S. Refutation


[1] Example taken from the VISA database: https://visa-video.ens-lyon.fr/visa-web/ (09-20-2017).


 

Derived Words

Argument from DERIVED WORDS

1. A seemingly analytical form

A derived word is a word formed from a base or a stem (root) word combined with a prefix or a suffix : Work, worker – (to) do, (to) undo
A derivational family is made up of all the words that are derived from the same root or base word.

The argument based on derived words uses this mechanism of morphological derivation. Since the signifier of the root word is found in the derived word, one might think that, « obviously », the meaning of the root word is also transferred to the derived word, which is not necessarily the case. The global statement is apparently undeniable, because it is true by virtue of its apparently analytical form, « A is A »:

I am human, nothing human is alien to me.

The president of a rather powerless conciliation commission of addressed his colleagues in this commission as commissioners; this clever label gives him and his colleagues the authority associated with the word (police) commissioner and a certain superiority over the people who appeal to the commission.

A famous speech by General de Gaulle uses such self-justifying statements:

As for the legislative elections, they will be held within the period established by the Constitution, unless the entire French people is to be gagged, prevented from speaking as they are prevented from living, by the same means that prevent students from studying, teachers from teaching and workers from working. (Charles de Gaulle, speech on May 30, 1968 [1])

In a well-made world, “students study, teachers teach and workers work” if not, the semantic disorder argues the abnormality of beings who don’t act according to the name of the category to which they indisputably belong. See Confucius on the Rectification of names.

2. Semantic differences between the root word and the derived word

The morphological similarity may hide deep semantic differences between the root word and the derived word, which meaning may range from the preservation of the root meaning, to the opposition of their connotations or argumentative orientations, to the complete independence of meanings in synchrony.

Different orientations of derived words

The French present participle adjective aliénant, “alienating”, and the past participle adjective aliéné, “alienated”, are morphologically derived from the verb aliéner, “to alienate”, but have two different meanings. Aliénant refers to socio-political conditions while aliéné refers to serious mental conditions.
In the following case, the speaker rejects a social claim by aligning the former with the latter:

If you find your work alienating [Fr. aliénant], then we will direct you to an asylum
[Fr. asile d’aliénés, « insane asylum »].

Anti-oriented derived words

By means of a kind of antanaclasis see Orientation Reversal, §1, the following exchange plays with the opposite argumentative orientations of words belonging to the same lexical family:

By signing this timely compromise, the president has made an opportune highly political decision.
Again, the president has compromised himself with his usual opportunistic, politicking!

Rebuttal

The argument by derivation is therefore refuted as a “play on words”, by pointing out the differences in meaning between the root word and the derived word. This rebuttal is in turn,  rejected as “semantic nitpicking”, see Expression.

2. Other designations and related forms

2.1 Aristotle, topos of derivation

Topos # 2 of Aristotle defines the “topos of derived words” as follows:

Another topic is derived from similar inflexions, for, in like manner, the derivative must either be predicable of the subject or not; for instance, that the just is not entirely good, for in that case good would be predicable of anything that happens justly; but to be justly put to death is not desirable. (Rhet., II, 23, 2; Freese, p. 297)

This is a dialectical exercise. Problem: “Is the just desirable?” that is to say, is the predicate « — is good, desirable » part of the essential definition of the word just? The answer is no, because “If you think that the just is desirable, then you think that being justly put to death is desirable”, which is rarely the case.

2.2 Cicero, topos of conjugata 

Cicero considers the same argumentative device under the label topic of related terms (coniugata), that is, « arguments based on words of the same family »; that is, terms such as “wise, wisely, wisdom” (Top., III, 12, p. 391):

If a field is “common” (compascuus), it is lawful to use it as a common pasture (compascere). (Ibid.)

Since it is a common field, the flock of any member of the community may graze there in common. But does this mean that all the flocks of the members of the community can graze there at the same time or one after the other?

2.3 Bossuet (1677): etymology, notatio nominis, conjugata

For Bossuet there are two kinds of topoi exploiting derivations.

1. The topos “drawn from etymology, in Latin notatio nominis, that is from the root from which the words come, like ‘to be a master, one must master the masters’.” (Bossuet 1677, ch. 20; example after Reverso; Fr. “if you are king [roi], then reign! [régnez]”).

The example corresponds to Cicero conjugata.

— On the other side, the scheme “taken from words that have all the same origin, called conjugata”, giving as an example of this relationship the pair homo / hominis, two inflected forms of the same word. (Id.). Unlike the case of lexical derived words, the meaning of the word does not vary according to its grammatical case.

The terminology may seem a bit confusing, but the bottom line is clear: whenever two terms are linked by morphology, lexicon or etymology, the conclusions drawn for one of the two can be applied to the other.


[1] Quoted after http://archives.charles-de-gaulle.org/pages/espace-pedagogique/le-point-sur/les-textes-a-connaitre/discours-du-30-mai-1968.php (11-08-2017)
[2] To rein (Fr. régner) Latin, regnum “royal authority”, “sovereignty”, “kingdom”, is derived from rex, regis “king” (Fr. roi)


 

Denying

DENYING:
« No! » / « Not-P »

A negative proposition E1 can be analysed as not-E° (but cf. 2.3). Total negation rejects as globally untrue, false, inadequate; it dismisses, turns down, refutes, rebuts, rectifies, … the primitive proposition .
Partial negation rectifies a segment or a feature of .

From the point of view of practical argumentation analysis, and following Ducrot (1972), there are three main types of sentence negation.

1. Dialogical negation

corresponds to an existing statement previously produced by another participant in the same linguistic action. This “confrontational metalinguistic negation” (Ducrot 1972, p. 38) is fundamental for refutation. Examples (after Ducrot, s. d).

— Rejecting an assertion:

S0   — The next presidential election will take place in two years
S0   — No, it will be next year.

— Rejecting a presupposition:

S0   — Peter has stopped smoking
S0   — No, Peter has never smoked.

— Correcting the degree:

S0   — The flood damage is considerable
S0:   — No, it is not considerable, it is negligible / catastrophic.

— Correcting a grammatical mistake:

S0   — Look at the childs!
S0:   —No, Not the childs, the children.

— Correcting of a contextual error:

Pupil to teacher: — Wyhh, it’s 3.30! (end of lesson; in a whining and demanding tone)
Teacher to pupil: — No, it’s not 3.30! (said in the same tone), it is 3.30 (said in a matter-of-fact and positive tone)

When working on a corpus of texts or argumentative interactions, the practical rule for the analyzing a negative statement E1 = “not ” is to search the previous context for an addressed statement (or something close to the semantic content of ). If there is one, then, E1 both rejects and rectifies E°. The precise nature of the correction can be specified, in the broad context of the argumentative question structuring the exchange.

can be in the “short” or “long” memory of the interaction. In the case of a complex argumentative situation, i.e. a question that is debated at different times, in different places according to different genres and formats, the discursive distance to retrieve may be quite long and the result dubious.

2 Polyphonic negation: E° is not recoverable in the context

There is no actual statement or semantic content corresponding to , for example when the speaker of E1 anticipates a foreseeable objection, S. Prolepsis. In this case, according to Ducrot’s original and robust version of the polyphonic nature of language, we can consider that the negative utterance articulates two voices, that of the rectifier and that of the rectified. As in the previous case, the speaker takes the position of the rectifier. Ducrot speaks in such cases of “conflictual polemical negation” (ibid.)

The two uses of negation, depending on whether is recoverable in the context or not, are perfectly continuous. If the statement is not recoverable in the available context, one will opt for a polyphonic analysis, referring the rejected content not to an actual participant, but to a potential participant, an indeterminate abstract voice, expressing something relevant to the dispute, S. Interaction, Dialogue, Polyphony. However, some doubt as will remain to the precise scope of the rectification effected by the negation.

3 Descriptive negation

Ducrot mentions the case of a “descriptive negation”, which cannot be divided into two antagonistic voices:

Some uses of a syntactically negative sentence have neither a conflictual nor an antagonistic character. The negation is used, so to speak, without paying attention to its negative character, without, therefore, introducing into it any idea of dispute or doubt. Thus, to indicate that today the weather is perfectly fine today, I can use a negative sentence “not a cloud in the sky” as well as a positive sentence “the sky is perfectly blue and clear”. (Ibid.)

« Peter is not stupid » can be understood as an admiring understatement of « Peter is really smart », or as an indignant rejection of another intervention implying that « Peter is dull ».

Such negative sentences have an autonomous meaning. This analysis is suitable for negative polarity items, i.e. words that occur only in negative clauses, without a corresponding positive clause.

You can’t hold a candle to him.

It is also appropriate for negative prefix words without corresponding positive terms (see above).

4. Negation [Verneinung]

The dialogic character of negation is systematically exploited in psychoanalysis, where the negative utterance is seen as the result of a negotiation between the conscious and the unconscious:

The way in which our patients present their associations during the work of analysis gives us the opportunity to make some interesting observations. “Now you are going to think I’m going to say something offensive, but I really don’ mean it.” We realize that this is rejection, by projection, of an idea that has just come up. Or, “You ask who this person in the dream can be. It’s not my mother.” We change this to: “So it is his mother.” In our interpretation we take the liberty of ignoring the negation and of picking out only the subject matter alone of the association. It is as though the patient had said: “it’s true that my mother came to my mind when I thought of this person, but I don’t feel inclined to let the association work.”

Thus, the content of a repressed image or idea can make its way into consciousness, on condition that it is negated. Negation is a way of taking cognizance of what is repressed; indeed it is already a release of the repression, though of course, not, an acceptance of what is repressed. We can see how this separates the intellectual function is separated from the affective process. (Freud, [1925], p. 235)

4. Argumentative strategies using various forms of negation

The relationship between discourse and counter-discourse is fundamental to the definition of an argumentative situation, negation and denial are therefore at the very foundation of argumentation studies.

 

See Contradiction; Non contradiction principle
Figures of Opposition
Opposite words;Opposites – A contrario —  Refutation by the opposite
Destruction of Speech; Objection; Refutation; Counter-argumentation.

Demonstration and Argumentation

DEMONSTRATION AND ARGUMENTATION

To demonstrate comes from the Latin demonstrare “to show, to point out”. The verbs to demonstrate and to show verbs are synonymous in some contexts: “In what follows, I’ll show (= demonstrate) that… ».
In ordinary life, people make demonstrations of friendship, solidarity, affection… they make an exhibition, a show of their feelings, as they give proofs of love.The word demonstration, even in its most abstract uses, keeps a link with the visual and pictorial; if a proof involves touching with the finger, a demonstration shows. Argumentation has no such metaphorical background.

In rhetoric, the word demonstration is used with two completely different meanings, in addition to the meaning of “proof”:
— A demonstration is a vivid representation of an event or a state of affairs as a picture, for an audience or a reader, who is put in the position of witness of the represented event. This figure is also called evidence or hypotyposis (Lausberg [1960], § 810).
The demonstrative genre is another name for the epideictic or panegyric or laudatory genre, together with the deliberative and judicial genres (Lausberg [1960], § 239).

Demonstration is often opposed to argumentation as defining two different cultures without contact and communication, the world of science vs. the world of human affairs, the world of truth vs. that of opinion. This popular opposition is often taken as a defining characteristic of argumentation. However, its content and actual scope, the precise relations between argumentation and demonstration, should be considered as an essential issue for the development of argumentation studies.

1. The hypothetico-deductive demonstration, the ideal of proof?

In logic, a demonstration is a discourse that proceeds from axioms to a theorem, according to specified rules of deduction. The construction of a demonstrative sequence is guided by intentionality, since it aims at a stopping point, a remarkable, detachable result, the theorem.

A proof is formalized when it can be presented as a mathematical demonstration. Formal proof is seen as characteristic of science as pure calculus, and is sometimes seen as the ideal of proof. This view contrasts with science as a description of reality (geography, zoology), or as a combination of calculation, observation and experiment (physics, chemistry).

In the sciences, a demonstration is a discourse, based on true propositions: (true by hypothesis; or as a result of observations or experiments carried out according to a validated protocol; or as a result obtained from previous demonstrations), and leading to a new, stable, true, proposition. Such a proposition marks a step forward in the field, and is likely to guide further developments in research.

Scientific practice involves many non-formal linguistic, cognitive or material operations, other than demonstration. Such operations might include grasping a situation, formulating a  problem, or a hypothesis, setting up an experiment, manipulating the objects and instruments, selecting, observing and describing the relevant data, making quantitative measurements and related calculations, checking the results, imagining new experiences, drawing conclusions, preparing the results for oral communication and publication, responding to the colleagues’ objections, revising the claims, and so on. We could add to this all the professional argumentative situations in which researchers have to apply for new funding, write or evaluate a research project or to recruit a new colleague. These argumentative operations require the coordinated management of technical, mathematical and natural languages, including a variety of semiotic media, figures, tables, schemes and diagrams. Natural language argumentation plays a key role in all these mixed activities.

2. Two distinct fields: What we know, what we do

Argumentation is concerned with what is to be believed, with the question of proof and demonstration, but goes beyond this. The exploratory function of argumentation extends beyond its epistemic role, to the practical discussion (internal or external) of what,  would be the most sensible next step given one’s current interests. One might ask for example, “should I apply for this or that job, buy this or that car, ignore or accept offers of negotiation”. And human affairs go even further, beyond the realm of practical decisions; generally speaking, argumentative situations arise as soon as any kind of choice is possible. Thus, argumentative situations can arise in relation to antagonistic feelings, to what is really worthy of admiration or love, see Emotions. In these areas the language of proof and demonstration does not make sense, whereas the language of argument does.

One might think that in the case of certain matters involving true beliefs and accurate scientific predictions, doubt is provisional, and that any doubt will be removed in the light of scientific progress. However, when considering situations involving human agents, however, doubt is an essential component. In such situations, it is often impossible to remove doubt completely, and it is legitimate to ask what would have happened if …

We turn to argumentation when the data are incomplete or of poor quality and the assumptions and laws are imperfectly defined; the conclusions are, therefore, subject to a constant principle of revision. As the last resort, we turn to the question of time: an argument is a bet. Combined with urgency and occasion, argumentation is a time-limited process, in contrast to the unlimited time afforded to the philosophical or scientific demonstration. There are essential differences in the modus operandi of argumentation and demonstration, in their fields of application and in the nature of the problems to which they can be applied.

When it operates in the field of knowledge, argumentation has an exploratory and creative function that goes beyond its demonstrative and critical function, see Abduction. Argumentation generates hypotheses, opens discussions and triggers the critical process of verification and revision.

Demonstration is by definition related to a domain; argumentation can combine heterogeneous evidence. Argumentation is the art of hierarchizing not only values,, but also types of evidence and articulating levels of demonstrations. If one wants to explore the possibilities and economic interests of a major environmental management project, such as, the construction of a canal between the Green and the Yellow Oceans, for example, then the technical evidence, solutions and objections of geologists, economists and ecologists must be articulated and confronted with those of neighbors, citizens, investors and politicians. Negotiation will take place in the face of calculations and technical evidence each as unique as the next, and argumentation in natural language will have to fully exercise its synthetical function.

3. Argumentation-proof and argumentation-demonstration:
The legacy

Several theories of otherwise very different orientations come together in order to oppose argumentation to demonstration. Historically, the notions of demonstration and argumentation inherited by the Western tradition were developed in ancient Greece. Demonstration in science and mathematics (Archimedes, Euclid) was constructed without reference to argumentation in social affairs. According to Lloyd, Aristotle elucidated “the explicit concept of rigorous proof” ([1990], p. 77) in a scientific context where four types of argument were currently in use:

The first of these is arguments in the legal and political domains, the second those in early Greek cosmology and medicine, the third mathematics in pre-Aristotelian period, and the fourth deductive arguments in philosophy. The first two relate primarily, to informal, the second pair to rigorous proof. (Ibid.)

The unity of the disciplines of proof can be shown by the examining their vocabulary:

The same vocabulary, not only of evidence, examination, judgment, but also proof, appears also outside the specifically legal or political domain, notably in a variety of contexts in early Greek speculative thought. Both cosmology and medicine, and some extended passages from the Hippocratic Corpus merit particular attention. (Id., p. 78)

In Aristotle’s work, persuasive rhetorical argumentation is characterized by its differences from valid logical demonstration (and probable dialectical deduction). Since then, argumentation has been conventionally associated with logical demonstration, to argumentation-demonstration, rather than to argumentation-proof such as exemplified in the practices of scientists, practitioners, historians, police investigators, etc. Argumentation is most closely associated with these practices, because of its non-formal nature and its relation to practical action. For example, the essential concept of the argumentative question is derived not from a logical concept, but from the medical descriptive concept of stasis, that is a state in which physiological fluids are blocked, and, metaphorically collaborative speech and action are suspended.

This non-operational opposition between demonstration and argumentation, which now functions as a commonplace, has been considerably reformulated and strengthened by the New Rhetoric, as well as by the non-referentialist positions of the theory of Argumentation within Language.

4. Demonstration versus argumentation?

Demonstration and logical proof are classically opposed to argumentation on the basis of their premises and modes of inference. But it goes much deeper than that. Natural language and discourse are inherently subjective, i.e. self- and we-related, focused on the “here” and “now”, see Subjectivity. Words allow for synonymy, homonymy and polysemy; their meaning depends on context. Syntactic constructions need to be interpreted. Discourse is figurative. Meaning and reference are negotiated and managed through principles of relevance. These processes are stigmatized as inherently “vague and elastic”; but the polymorphism of language should also be praised for its adaptability to new situations and its capacity to change the rules

On a more general level, it should be noted, first, that there is no reason to favor elementary logical demonstration over other scientific activities, of which it is certainly a prominent member. Secondly, oppositions only make sense only if the opposed fields are comparable. Experimentation, mathematics, computerization, have moved apart the techno-sciences worlds, and it makes little sense to compare an article in a scientific journal publishing cutting-edge research with arguments developed in a newspaper column..

4.1 The New Rhetoric

Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca’s Treatise has constructed a powerful, autonomous concept of argument on the one hand, by excluding emotion from the field of argument, and on the other by pitting argumentation against demonstration. The purpose of the Treatise is to circumscribe an autonomous discursive domain, in which speech develops cut off from demonstration and emotion. In the very words of the Treatise, the pair argumentation / demonstration functions as an “antithetical pair” (Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca [1958], p. 422.), whose terms are the subject of a genuine “breaking of links” or “dissociation” (ibid. p. 411 sq.). Systematically, the Treatise opposes argumentation to demonstration, as can be seen in every occurrence of the word demonstration mentioned in the index. This strategy, is a cornerstone of the Treatise.

The fundamental question of the difference between the language of argumentation, natural language and the language of demonstration, formal language, is not addressed. In the Treatise, the form of demonstration as opposed to argumentation is taken in a particular discipline, formal logic, which would be prototypical of demonstration as the inaccessible ideal of argumentation. This hardened and simplistic image of demonstration encourages the antagonism between argument and demonstration, and leads to the exclusion  from the Treatise of all that concerns sciences :

We seek here to construct such a theory [of argumentation] by analyzing the methods of proof used in the human sciences, law and philosophy. We shall examine arguments put forwards by advertisers in their newspapers, politicians in speeches, lawyers in pleadings, judges in decisions, and philosophers in treatises ([1958], p. 10)

No reference is made to any kind of scientific activity. Argumentation concerns only human affairs only, and demonstration concerns only mathematics and science. The gap between “the two cultures” (Snow, 1961) is thus at the very foundation of argumentation as a discipline.

4.2 The Argumentation within Language theory

This theory argues that the argumentative orientation is an essential feature of the semantic level of language, and concludes that it is impossible to develop arguments as good reasons in discourse and interaction. Consider the following passage:

It has often been remarked that discourses concerning everyday life cannot achieve “demonstrations” in the logical sense of the word. Already Aristotle noted that the necessary demonstration of the syllogism contrasts with the incomplete and only probable argumentation of the enthymeme. Perelman, Grize, Eggs insisted on this idea. At first I thought that I was merely following this tradition, and that my only originality lay in pointing out to  the nature of language the necessity of substituting argumentation for demonstration. I thought that the words of language were the cause or the sign of the fundamentally rhetorical, or, as we said, the “argumentative”, character of discourse. But now I am led to say much more. Not only do words not permit demonstration, but they do not permit that degraded form of demonstration which would be argumentation. Argumentation is only a dream of discourse, and our theory should rather be called « the theory of non-argumentation” (Ducrot 1993, p. 234).

Argumentation is in language, not in discourse. Since Ducrot’s structuralist framework reduces the order of speech to that of language (Saussurian langue), it is quite coherent to deny any specific principle of organization to reasoned discourse.

5. How to argue the (non-)demonstrative character of argumentation?

The refutation of the possible demonstrative nature of ordinary discourse is threatened by skeptical paradoxes and is subject to self-refutation. It is difficult to argue about the argumentative or non-argumentative character of natural language discourse, while using natural language discourse.

Interaction studies have taught us a great deal about what everyday discourse can achieve. Short, local inferences are developed in sequences that combine language and action into operational conclusions.. We define, categorize, articulate causes and effects, make analogies,  all of which are more or less inadequate, but all of which are open to criticism and correction. Sometimes, these result in satisfaction for all i.nvolved

WIth a few conventions and adjustments, more sophisticated episodes or reasoning  can be developed in ordinary language. If the syllogism constitutes an example of a necessary demonstration, since the syllogism consists of a sequence of utterances in natural language, words at least allow syllogistic demonstration. Figures and arithmetic are not entirely foreign to natural language, which also allows for some correct geometrical conclusions, so that the tenon fits the mortise exactly. Not only a logic, but also an everyday geometry, arithmetic, physics… underpin linguistic practices, and no metaphysical deficiency prevents them from drawing correct conclusions, as the following little calculation shows:

The Abbé du Chaila was one of the main architects of the repression of the Protestants in the Cévennes, in the south of France. His assassination was at the origin of the Camisards’ war, in the 18th century.
The date of birth of the future abbot of Chaila remains a mystery, due to the disappearance of the parish registers. It must have been at the beginning of 1648. In fact, François’s parents, Balthazar de Langlade and Francoise d’Apchier, were married on the 9 April 1643 and had eight boys and two girls in ten years, at a rate of one child per year. François being the fifth child of the family was thus born in 1648, the four previous brothers having been born in 1644, 1645, 1646 and 1647.

Robert Poujol, [The Abbé du Chaila (1648-1702)], 2001[1].

Any claim about the (non-)demonstrative character of argumentation in general is difficult to assess, regardless of the prestige of the authorities supporting it. Arguments from natural signs, case-by-case arguments cannot be treated as appeals to authority or arguments by analogy. Ordinary argumentative discourse can combine quite heterogeneous types of argument and fields of evidence, including technical and scientific episodes. One can argue properly in natural language; sometimes, some truth emerges from legal and historical debates if they are properly framed and managed; and argumentation plays a role in the learning of science.

6. Argumentation in science education

There are other links to be found between argumentation and scientific activities. The golden rule is given by Quine who uses it to construct his formal logic:

This course is prompted by an inclination to work directly with ordinary language until there is a clear gain in departing from it. (1980, p. x).

By the same token, the teaching and learning of scientific method is necessarily grounded in natural language and everyday argumentation, and departs from it when there is a clear advantage in doing so.
Scientific proof can be seen both as a finished product, impeccably presented in published papers and textbooks; and as a process, that leaves room for dialogue, argument correction and development. Argumentation is on the side of the process, its claims are in the making.

This leads to a focus on argumentation as an instrument for science education (Erduran & Jiménez-Aleixandre 2007). Scientific “enculturation” in general, debates on socio-scientific issues are now key domains of argumentation studies. These research programs on argumentation in science education and argumentation on socio-scientific issues, emerged in the late 1990s and early 2000s. They now represent a key field of development for argumentation studies.

The humanities remain largely trapped in a conception of argumentation based on logocentric discourses, in which anything and everything can be claimed. An antagonism has developed from this conception, with “logical demonstration” serving as a convenient antagonist. The repositioning of argumentation as a complex, combinatorial activity that seeks to manage heterogeneous evidence in possibly complex material contexts allows us to distance ourselves from this traditional logocentric exclusivity. Discussions between two mechanics disagreeing about how to repair a faulty engine, or between two students disagreeing about the shape of the rays coming out of the lens are as prototypical of an argumentative situation as any ideological debate.


[1] Poujol R. L’ Abbé du Chaila (1648-1702). Montpellier: Les Presses du Languedoc, 2001. P. 31.

[2] Arsac Gilbert, Chapiron Gisèle, Colonna Alain, Germain Gilles, Guichard Yves, Mante Michel 1992  Initiation au raisonnement déductif au collège. Lyon, Presses Universitaires de Lyon
Baker M. J. (1996). Argumentation et co-construction des connaissances. Interaction et Cognitions 2, 3. 157-191.
Buty Chr. & Plantin Chr. (2009). Argumenter en Classe de Sciences. Du débat à l’Apprentissage. Lyon: ENS Éditions.
De Vries E., Lund K., & Baker M. J. (2002). Computer-mediated epistemic dialogue: explanation and argumentation as vehicles for understanding scientific notions. The Journal of the Learning Sciences 11, 1. 63-103.
Polo Claire, 2020. Le Débat fertile. Explorer une controverse dans l’émotion Grenoble: Université Grenoble Alpes Éditions


 

Definition (4): Persuasive Definition

« PERSUASIVE DEFINITION »

Stevenson ([1938]) introduced the concept of persuasive definition in the following terms:

In any “persuasive definition” the term defined is a familiar one, whose meaning is both descriptive and strongly emotive. The purport of the definition is to alter the descriptive meaning of the term, usually by giving it greater precision within the boundaries of its customary vagueness; but the definition does not make any substantial change in the term’s emotive meaning. And the definition is used, consciously or unconsciously, in an effort to secure, by this interplay between emotive and descriptive meaning, a redirection of people’s attitudes. (Stevenson [1938], p. 210-211)

For a definition to be persuasive, in Stevenson’s sense, its descriptive content must be redefined, while its « emotional force » must remain intact, so that it can be applied to the redefined content. Stevenson gives the following example; A and B are “discussing a mutual friend”  – let’s call him Z (id, p. 211.)

A points out a number of deficiencies in person Z (education, conversation, literary references, subtlety of mind) and concludes that “he is definitely lacking in culture.”

B describes Z in a number of positive terms (imagination, sensitivity, originality) and concludes that “he is a man of far deeper culture than many of us who have had superior advantages in education”.

First, both A and B value culture, and are willing to give the word culture and the judgment “Z is a cultured person” a positive emotional orientation. Moreover, the word culture has a vague descriptive sense; B carves out a new definition from this descriptive sense, and shows that it fits their mutual friend Z. Stevenson analyzes B’s argumentative move as follows

His purpose was to redirect A‘s attitudes, feeling that A was insufficiently appreciative of their friend’s merits (id., p. 211).

The argumentative trick – according to Stevenson – is at point (b):

(a) B wants to value Z.
(b) He redefines culture “within the boundaries of its customary vagueness” according to the qualities his friend possesses;
(c) and he concludes that his friend is cultured;
(d) and the friend benefits from the positive opinion associated with the idea of culture and the cultured person.

Thus, a persuasive definition redefines the descriptive content of a term not on the basis of context-free, objective general considerations, but with a view to applying that term to a predetermined person, a known singular case. This would make it misleading.

Point (d) implies that the argumentative orientation (here called  “the emotive content”) is independent of the cognitive content, and not affected by the redefinition. Thus, this orientation must be attached directly to the signifier.

A persuasive definition is a definition that does not meet the condition of separability between, on the one hand, the construction process of the definition, and, on the other hand, the use of the definitional features to include an individual or a special case in the category it determines and to call him by the name corresponding to this category. In other words, a persuasive definition is an ad hoc definition.

But was this definition dreamed up by B in order to save their friend Z from the very negative assessment he is receiving from his other “friend” A?
Rather, this definition seems to be a step in the evolution of the notion of culture, which will lead to the multiple definitions of the word in the dictionary by 2025, where the traditional definition will take second place see Merriam-Webster, Culture.
This exchange is merely a moment of confrontation between two definitions that will end up side by side

A perfect argumentative situation

It could be argued that A, in order to categorize Z, uses the traditional definition of culture as literary references, etc., also carved out of the vague meaning of « culture », « within the limits of its customary vagueness ». Because of its traditional prestige, this definition of « culture » , is considered true and self-evident, and the common friend is excluded from the circle of the cultivated / cultured people.
So A uses the traditional definition of culture to exclude Z from the cultured category, just as B uses a renovated definition to include Z in that category.
In short, we have a perfect stasis of definition that has created an argumentative situation in which A tries to influence B as much as B tries to influence A in their mutual visions of their friend B.
It should be noted, however, that the narrator, Stevenson, attributes a convincing definition only to B. A is the only partner who does not try to persuade, but simply tells the truth.This is a typical maneuver by an ally of A.

A parallel case could be imagined about the criteria of what constitutes “good schoolwork”.

The teacher’s definition: The value of a schoolwork is determined by its content (knowledge-based assessment)
Parent’s education-based definition: A good schoolwork is one in which students are engaged and working hard. My son spent his weekend working on his history class. He turned in an excellent paper, and deserves a good grade. (educationnally-based evaluation)

The parent’s definition could be considered biased just like B‘s definition of culture was in the previous case. The category “is a good school assignment” has been redefined to apply to Mr. Doe’s son, without regard to the content of the paper, which has traditionally been considered as the deciding factor. The target has been redesigned to fit the arrow, and the archer’s limited skills. Or not.

Clearly the parent also has a good educational case. Some negotiation is needed, as it was in the previous case.


 

Definition 3: Argumentations Exploiting a Definition

DEFINITION 3
Argument from DEFINITION

1. Definition in the process of categorization

Categorization is the process by which an individual is identified as belonging to a category, and is given the name of that category, S. Categorization and Nomination. The definition is the reservoir of essential characteristics that allow this identification.

2. Argumentation on the basis of a definition

The definition (the definiens) of a word or an expression (boy, scotch bonnet, democracy, single parent, educated person, British citizen, natural disaster …) provides a stock of definitional features applicable to all the beings, individuals, institutions, events … designated by the definiendum (belonging to the category named by the word). Argumentation by definition applies the definition of the name to an entity designated by that name. It works as follows:

    1. An argument: a statement of the form “I is a D”: I is an individual (identified, categorized, perceived, named… as) “a D”.
    2. A license to infer, found in the definition of D that is taken as authoritative.
    3. A conclusion: everything that is said about the D can be really be said of I.

A definition (a definiens) is a rich set of propositions about “what that kind of being is”. It contains doxical assertions based on common knowledge about those beings which are found in the examples that illustrate the definiens as well as in the definiens properly said. To call a being “a D” is to ascribe to it all the properties that define the name “D”, as well as the scripts, duties and obligations associated with Ds. In other words, the definition (the definiens) of “what is a D” is a set of inference licenses applicable to all the persons and objects called D.

Using the definition allows inferences of the following type, S. Common Place.

— “Harry is a British citizen”: this claim expresses a categorization of the person Harry, derived from the information that he was born in Bermuda, see Layout. The categorization (“— is a British citizen”) corresponds to a local modeling of the person “as a British citizen”, which makes it accessible to the inferential definition machine. Armed with this information, we can draw from the body of knowledge that defines “what it is to be an Englishman”, and conclude, according to the needs of the moment, that:

He takes tea at five
He will need a drop of milk
We can certainly address him in English
If he has committed a crime abroad, his legal treatment will be conducted according to the relevant international convention

— “My dear, you’re a little girl!” Traditional wisdom says that girls are like this, should do this and that, etc. Well, my daughter, you’re like this, and you must act accordingly:
— “This is a Scotch bonnet” so, it is “very aromatic, it is delicious prepared in an omelette”; better still, you can “dry it out, and use it as an aromatic[1], S. Categorization.
— “Now you are undoubtedly one of the great democracies” so we can re-establish diplomatic relations and encourage our citizens to spend their vacations on your beaches.
— “Mrs. Doe is a mother who lives alone”, so under such and such administrative and financial rules, she is entitled to a single parent allowance of a certain amount.
— “Mrs. Smith is a graduate student” so she enjoys certain rights and must fulfill certain obligations as defined by the Graduate Students Charter in effect at the university where she is enrolled.
— “He’s a bastard” so I don’t trust him.

Argumentation by definition ascribes to a particular being a quality that is actually found in the definition of its name, as found in a dictionary or an encyclopedia. More broadly, it ascribes to a being any characteristic that is borrowed from the stereotypical notion of the kind of beings that bear that name.
Argumentation by definition is the epitome of what Billig calls “bureaucratic thinking”, which is fundamental in everyday life (Billig [1987], p. 124).

When the criteria used for categorization are defined within a rigorous scientific framework, then argument by definition becomes an essential scientific tool. Similarly, in the field of law, the criteria that qualify an act make it possible to apply the legal syllogism, that provides routine legal decisions by default.

3. Argument from definition: Lexical definitions as inferential resources

Some basic argumentative inferences embedded in a word are made explicit in its lexical definition and suggested in the examples of its use. Language dictionaries are repositories of accepted ideas and accepted connections between ideas; as such, they provide legitimate inferences from and to a word in the language and culture to which they belong (Raccah 2014) see Orientation. These inferences are considered rational and persuasive insofar as they are expressions of a shared semantic heritage, the treasury of discursive rationality. Consider the word rich. By collating the definitions of some current dictionaries, we can gain some insight into the elementary “licenses to infer”, diversions, or “drifts” to and from this word, that is, the semantic inferences that characterize a basic understanding of the word “rich”. The following information is taken from definitions from MW, tfd; CD.

(i) … so he is rich. This claim is justified:

— On an analytical basis: … (he has) a lot of money; of valuable assets, SO he is rich
— On the basis of signs: … (he owns) expensive materials, workmanship (such as mahogany furniture), SO, he is rich
— On the basis of his or her moral character and motives:

He is determined to become rich quickly,  SO, he is likely to become rich

 (ii) He is rich, soOn the same analytical basis, or from the signs, one can deduce:

(he has) a lot of money; of valuable assets
… (he owns) expensive materials, workmanship (such as mahogany furniture)
… he does not have to work
… he has forgotten his humble background 

This last conclusion allows for exceptions: He is rich, but

… even when he became rich and famous, he never forgot his humble background.

(iii) An implicit principle, the “anyone can get rich” principle, eliminates two objections:

Having a humble background:
Even though he became rich and famous, he never forgot his humble background:

Lack of formal education:
A lack of formal education is not an obstacle to getting rich.

(iv) One main opposition: The rich vs. the poor, allows the application of the topos of the opposites:

There’s one law for the rich and another for the poor.


[1] Entry Mousseron in J. and J. Manuel Montegut (1975). Atlas des Champignons [Atlas of Mushrooms] Paris: Globus, 1975.


 

Correlative Terms

CORRELATIVE TERMS

Correlative terms are also called relative or reciprocal terms, and may be considered as opposite terms. Mother and child are correlative terms, that is, they are linked by the immediate inference:

if A is the mother of B, then B is the child of A

Correlative terms are defined by reference to one another; mother is defined as “woman with children”; child as “son or daughter of M”.
The following terms are correlatives:

cause / effect                  double / half                  master /slave
action / passion              sell / buy

Generally speaking, two predicates R1 and R2 are in a correlation relation when

A_R1_B <=> B_R2_A
A_mother_B <=> B_child_A

 “By definition, correlatives are opposites”; they are “ontologically simultaneous” (Hamelin [1905], p. 133). The topic of the correlative is n°3 on Aristotle’s list:

Another line of proof is based upon correlative ideas (Rhet, II, 23, 3; RR, p. 357)

The topic is exemplified by the enthymemes:

Where it is right to command obedience, it must have been right to obey the command.

 The tax-farmer: ”if it is no disgrace for you to sell it, it is no disgrace for us to buy it” (ibid.).

These inferences have limitations:

If it is legal/tolerated to buy 2 g of marijuana, then one may sell 2 g of marijuana.

But what about “possessing” and “buying”?

if it is legal/tolerated to possess 2g of marijuana,
then it is legal/tolerated to buy 2 g,
then it is legal/tolerated to sell it

given that for me, the only way to get marijuana is to buy it. But the law can make a distinction between two kinds of “possession”: the possession of drugs for private consumption is not an offence, while possession for trafficking is.

The following case deals with two pairs of correlatives, know / learn, and order / obey, articulated by the topic of the opposites:

If you want to command, you must first learn to obey.
The executive, when he was on his way up, had to learn to obey so that he should know how to command (quoted in Linguee).

Definition 2: Argumentation Justifying a Definition

DEFINITION 2
Arguments justifying a DEFINITION

1. Methods for constructing a sound definition

Definitions based on common usage, on the true meaning of the word, on the scientific meaning of the word can be pitted against each other.

There are rules for establishing a correct definition, and therefore, critical rules for evaluating, definitions, see Arguments establishing vs. exploiting a relationship.
These rules depend on the social or scientific fields to which the defined entities belong, and adapt to the different types of definitions. The more general ones are.

(i) Does the definition correctly disambiguate the term according to its meanings (homonymy) and acceptances (polysemy)? see Ambiguity.

(ii) Does the definition avoid circularity? If not, it is a vicious circle. Since words are defined by words, the whole dictionary is actually circular. As explanations or arguments in general, definitions should try to avoid circularity as much as possible; that is, the definition (definiens) cannot use the word it is supposed to define (definiendum), nor a (near) synonym of the word. Nevertheless, a definition by synonyms or by the simple negation of an antonym is helpful if one of these defining words is better known than the definiendum.

(iii) Does the definition cover all  uses of the word? Does the meaning of a passage remain the same if the definiens is replaced by the definiendum? If not, the definition should be revised.

(iv) Does the definition make it possible to distinguish those entities that are called by that name from those that are not? A definition can be criticized for being too broad (it applies to heterogeneous objects or beings) or for being too narrow (it excludes objects or beings that it would be desirable to include). see Definition and Argument, § 2, for the role of ostension and exemplification.

(v) Does it help? That is, does it provide enough information to clarify the meaning of the word, and, if necessary, does it give some functional clues, or point to the scientific or technical uses of the word?

(vi) Is the definition concise, clear, and simple? Does it use unknown, obscure or ambiguous words?

(vii) Is the definition objective? Does it exclude the speaker’s value judgments and ideological preferences about the entities or qualities being defined? see Orientation; Persuasive definitions.

Methods and rules such as those mentioned above serve as a guide for making definitions and, consequently, for criticizing them.
— The following set of available arguments in their positive form argue that the definition is sound, and in their negative form they argue that the definition is unsound.

(i) it correctly disambiguates the definiens
(ii) It avoids circularity
(iii) It covers all the uses of the word
(iv) It is neither too broad nor too narrow
(v) It is helpful
(vi) It is concise, clear, and simple
(vii) It is objective.

— These arguments are mobilized in debates about definitions (Schiappa 1993; 2000), that is, when there is a stasis of definition (see infra), see True meaning of a word
— They are fundamental to the criticism of argumentations that use a definition, showing for example that the underlying definitions are poorly constructed and do not follow this or that rule.

2. Stasis of definition

A definitional stasis occurs when it appears that discourse and counter-discourse appear to be based on incompatible definitions of the same object:

S1: — The right to freedom of speech and demonstration is fundamental to democracy.
S2: —
What is fundamental in a democracy, is the right to have an iPhone and something to eat.

A definitional question arises: which features are essential (central) features and which ones are incidental (peripheral) to characterize a democratic state?

Incompatible categorizations lead in a question of definition:

S1:      — Accidental death of a Syldavian diplomat
S2:      — Assassination of a Syldavian diplomat

Classified information has been leaked:
S1:      — A new manifestation of the malfunctioning of the Syldavian services
S2:      — There are traitors within our services.

The investigator, in the role of the third party, transforms the two conflicting discourses into an argumentative question, and initiates an investigation to clarify what happened, based on legal definitions:

What is murder? What is an accident?
What are the crucial differences between negligence and treason?

The stasis of definition can develop as follows:

S11: — Syldavia is now a real democracy now!
S21: — How dare you talk about democracy in a country that does not recognize the rights of minorities?
S12: — According to the dictionary, democracy is …; nothing in this definition mentions the rights of minorities; so, Syldavia is certainly a true democracy
S22: — This definition is bad, and ideologically biased.

— The confrontation between the positions S11 and S21 raises a question of categorization.
S12 rejects S21‘s objection by referring to the dictionary; he or she could just as well have referred to the accepted conventions, international law, consensus, etc.
S22 ratifies the definitional deadlock.

According to Humpty Dumpty, the best way to resolve of a definitional stasis is to appeal to power:

[Humpty Dumpty] […] — and that shows that there are three hundred and sixty-four days when you might get un-birthday presents—”
“Certainly,” said Alice.
“And only one for birthday presents, you know. There’s glory for you!”
“I don’t know what you mean by ‘glory’”, Alice said.
Humpty Dumpty smiled contemptuously. “Of course, you don’t – till I tell you. I meant ‘there’s a nice knock-down argument for you!”’
“But ‘glory’ doesn’t mean ‘a nice knock-down argument,’” Alice objected.
“When I use a word,” Humpty Dumpty said in rather a scornful tone, “it means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less.”
“The question is,” said Alice, “whether you can make words mean so many different things.”
“The question is,” said Humpty Dumpty, “which is to be master—that’s all.”
Alice was too much puzzled to say anything, so after a minute Humpty Dumpty began again. […]
Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass, 1872 [1]


[1] Quoted after Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass. Chapter 6, Humpty-Dumpty. 2016. No pag. http://www.gutenberg.org/files/12/12-h/12-h.htm#link2HCH0006. (11-08-2017)

Definition 1: Definition and Argument

DEFINITION 1
DEFINITION AND ARGUMENT

1. Defining definition

The definition of a word is a description of its meaning(s) in relation to its use(s).

Not only words but also phrases need to be defined. Fixed or semi-fixed phrases, that is idiomatic expressions, (beating around the bush), need to be defined, because their global meaning does not result from the mechanical combination of the meanings of their components.
Moreover, social life produces conventional expressions that are used with a specific meaning  that requires a definition:

What is a single parent?
What is an emergency situation? An urgent case?

Depending on the nature of the word and the circumstances of the questioning, these questions ask for the meaning of the word, or for information about the kind of object to which the word refers, or about the circumstances in which it is possible to use the word.
In argumentative situations, even the meaning of current words may be in dispute: What is an educated person?

The meaning of a word in ordinary language is not a “backstage spirit” animating the word, but a discourse “equivalent”; “having the same meaning”:

uncle                      =      “mother’s or father’s brother”
[definiendum]       =      [definiens]

The definition establishes a semantic equivalence between a word, the definiendum, “that which is  is to be defined”, the dictionary entry, and a discourse, the definiens “that which defines” (sometimes called “definition” by metonymy).
The definiens is a discourse that answers questions such as “what does the word X mean?” “What is X?”

From a logical point of view, the equivalence definiendum / definiens satisfies two requirements, one semantic and one formal.
— In semantic terms (intension) definiens and definiendum must have the same meaning.
— In formal terms (extension), the definiens and definiendum must be interchangable in all contexts, the global meaning of the passage remaining the same.
The definition is substituted for the word defined, when the discourse containing that word needs to be clarified; the word is substituted for its definition when the discourse needs to be shortened.

Beyond its semantics and lexicological characteristics, the definition of “fish” as a species of animal draws on the field of natural science. The definition of “democracy”, “citizen” and “citizenship”, combines political science and political and ideological ideals. The definition of “single parent” refers to laws and regulations. The vague concept of a “cultured person” will combine a little of all the arts and letters. Advances in knowledge, history, and variations in usage will change the meaning of the words and the kinds of beings and objects they refer to.

Argumentative situations will destabilize the meaning of words, and the definition of commonly used words may require revision and further clarification.

2. Types of definition

Different methods can be used to construct a sound definition of a word, see Arguments Establishing vs Exploiting a relationship. They suggest criteria that come to the fore when the meaning of a word is at stake, when one wants to destabilize an unsatisfactory definition, or when one wants to justify a challenged one.

2.1 OstensionIndicating the meaning of a word or a phrase

Ostension is a gesture, the act of showing someone a concrete object. To defining a concrete noun by ostension is to show a sample of the object or beings being referred to:

You want to know what a duck is? Well, look at that one just flying by!

Ostension underlies the famous argument:

I cannot explain how, but I know a boletus badius when I see one!

Ostensive definitions can only be applied to concrete beings that are materially present in the context of speech. Ostension is fundamentally ambiguous: the same gesture shows the chestnut horse and its chestnut color, but it is disambiguated by the context.
Ostension bypasses meaning; it lacks the discursive element considered essential for a proper definition.
Ostension is an important tool for defining concrete things. The more the concrete object or being resembles the prototype of its category, the more effective ostension will be.

2.2 Focusing on the referential capacities of the word

The consideration of a variety of cases is crucial for the critique of definition: Does the definition under scrutiny allow us to refer correctly to all the entities or cases currently referred to by the corresponding name? S. Arguments to justify a definition.

2.2.1 Definition by exemplification

Definition by exemplification approaches the meaning of a word by giving an example of its use:

What is a hoax? Well, that is, for example, remember when reputable media announced that blonds would disappear by 2202? [1]

The example given, if prototypical, provides a good basis for understanding the meaning of the word.

2.2.2 Definition by enumeration (in extension)

Definitions in extension proceed by the enumerating all the individuals to which the word or expression refers to. Thus, the expression “conventional binary logic connector” is defined in extension as a member of the set {~, &, V, W, →}, S. Connective
A democracy is a state mentioned in the list of democracies established in the Democracy Dictionary:

Syldavia is a democracy because it is on the “Democracy List”.

The definition by extension provides the basis for case-by-case arguments. If “honestly acquired money” is defined as acquired “either through work, inheritance, financial investment, or winning the lottery”, then it can be indirectly proven that a sum of money is ill-gotten by showing that it was neither acquired by work, nor by inheritance, nor is the legitimate product of a financial investment, and so on.

2.3 Definition and instructions for use

2.3.1 Operational definition

An operational definition associates a notion X with a set of operations that make it possible permitting to determine whether or not that individual is an X. An operational definition does not say what X is in essence; it simply indicates how to find all individuals to which X refers.

The term “prime number” is defined as “a number which is divisible only by itself and by the unit”. This definition unambiguously determines whether or not a given number is a prime or not.

2.3.3 Functional definitions

As operational definitions, functional definitions do not consider the ature, or the technical design of the named instrument. The referent is characterized in terms of its functions, goals, objectives. Knowing what a compass is, is knowing that, it points (magnetic) north, and is used accordingly.

2.4 Describing the meaning of the word

2.4.1 Essentialist definition (definition in intension)

Essentialist definitions require that the definition “focus on the essence (and not the accident), and proceed by the next genus and specific difference” (Chenique 1975, p. 117).  An individual is given the name of its category, identified by a set of generic characteristics common to its parent genus and differentiating characteristics that specify its species, see Classification.

Essentialist definitions work well for natural species. In general vocabulary, the contrast is between central and peripheral characteristics. A dictionary of Syldavian institutions would include an entry “President of the Syldavian Republic (SR)”, defined by his or her mode of election, constitutional role etc. These core elements can be supplemented by anecdotal characteristics, such as “lives in the Parnassus Palace”; “her spouse is called ‘the first lady or man of Syldavia’”, etc. The latter information refers unambiguously to the President (it applies to him or her and only to him or her, the condition of substitutability is fulfilled), but doesn’t contribute to the clarification of the meaning of “President of the SR”. From the Aristotelian point of view,, free accommodation at the Parnassus Palace is not an essential characteristic of the office of President of the SR.

Essentialist definitions try to express the true meaning of the word, which corresponds to the very nature of the things it designates, i.e. their permanent essence. They go beyond the linguistic knowledge of the word (lexical definition), and even beyond the knowledge of the things defined (encyclopedic definition), always reflecting an imperfect state of knowledge.
In Platonic terms, an essentialist definition claims to retain the idea of ​​the thing: “What is virtue?”. In theory, the essentialist definition is governed by a methodology, based on an “intuition of the essence of the thing”, S. Classification. Ancient dialectic was the instrument used to construct correct essentialist definitions.

While a pragmatic definition of the word democracy is based on the many socio-historical uses of the word, an essentialist definition seeks to establish the ideal, essential characteristics of democracy, sometimes condemning current uses of the word in the name of “true democracy”, S. True meaning. It may be that no real democracy corresponds to the essence of democracy. The essentialist definition is used as an important critical tool in idealist or conservative argumentation (Weaver 1953). 

2.4.2 Lexicographic definition

Lexicographic definitions are found in language dictionaries, as opposed to encyclopedic dictionaries. Language dictionaries must meet several conditions:

— Collect all the words and idioms of a language (or the vocabulary used at a given time).
— Provide a description of their various meanings, their usage in speech, and their stereotypical figurative usage.
— Give the typical contexts of use associated with these meanings.
— Give the syntactic constructions that correspond to these meanings.
— Locate them in the different semantic fields to which they belong, i.e. indicate their relationships with their (quasi-) synonyms and antonyms, and their position in their derivational families.

The dictionary is a highly legitimated and legitimating institution. From the perspective of argumentation studies, since lexical meaning is inferential, the dictionary should be seen first and foremost as a vast store of “inferring principles”, S. Argumentation based on a definition (3).

Linguistic definitions draw simultaneously on different kinds of definitions. Knowledge of words (lexical definitions) and knowledge of things (encyclopedic scientific definitions) are theoretically clearly separated. However, they are, inextricably linked for current terms that have an encyclopedic definition. “When the barometer falls, the weather turns bad”: is this deduction supported by a meteorological physical law that expresses knowledge about the variations in atmospheric pressure? Or is it contained in the linguistic meaning of the word? To knowi the functional meaning of the word “barometer” is to know that “when it falls, the weather turns bad.”

All words are worthy of a lexical definition, but only those that have “plenty of being” are worthy of scientific knowledge, and are registered in the encyclopedia. The boundary between the two categories is unstable and depends on the state of research; conversation, once considered a futile and elusive thing, has been fruitfully conceptualized  by conversation analysis and ethnomethodology. These sciences have given “more being” to their object.

 2.4.3 Scientific definition of concepts and lexicographic definition of words

Encyclopedias collect only conceptual terms. Encyclopedic definitions summarize the state of knowledge about things and concepts referred to by the term. A good definition of a thing stabilizes a well-constructed knowledge.
Scientific definitions may use a redefined common term, (see infra stipulative definitions). The the physicist’s mass is not the dictionary’s mass:

In physics, mass is a property of a physical body. It is the measure of an object’s resistance to acceleration (a change in its state of motion) when a force is applied. It also determines the strength of its mutual gravitational attraction to other bodies. In the theory of relativity, a related concept is the mass-energy content of a system. The SI unit of mass is the kilogram (kg). (Wikipedia, Mass).

In common language, the word mass is defined and illustrated as follows,

1
a: a quantity or aggregate of matter usually of considerable size
b (1): expanse, bulk — (2): massive quality or effect — (3): the main part or body <the great mass of the continent is buried under an ice cap (…) (4): aggregate, whole <men in the mass>
c: the property of a body that is a measure of its inertia and that is commonly taken as a measure of the amount of material it contains and causes it to have weight in a gravitational field
2
: a large quantity, amount, or number <a mass of material>
3
a: a large body of persons in a group <a mass of spectators>
b: the great body of the people as contrasted with the elite —often used in plural <the underprivileged and disadvantaged masses (…) (MW, Mass)

Arguments that establish a scientific definition of things are domain dependent. It took an astronomy conference was necessary to redefine the term planet, and end the controversy over the status of Pluto.

The common definition can be hardly recognizable under the technical definition. The following definition corresponds to an everyday experience:

1. A blocking of the alpha activity preceded by a transitional element that is expressed in the cortex region (a temporal tip-cortex)
2. A more or less pronounced twitch (a start);
3. Neurovegetative events, such as tachycardia and decreased skin resistance.
So, I was referring to the “classic” surprise reaction that you all know.
Henri Gastaud, [Discussion], 1974[1]

This is a scientific definition of surprise, “in the sense of ‘surprise reaction’ that is to say the set of phenomena observed by the neurophysiologist, when a sudden unexpected stimulus occurs” (Ibid.).

2.5 Stipulative definition, neology and baptism

Stipulative definitions are also called “definition of name”:

The only definitions recognized in geometry are what the logicians calls definitions of names, that is, the arbitrary application of names to things which are clearly designated by perfectly known terms. (Pascal Geom., p. 525)

They play a key role in the scientific creation of words. When a new class of phenomena or beings has been identified and characterized, they must be given a name. While in the general case, the process of definition begins with a given term and seeks to clarify its pre-established definition, stipulative definitions begin with a clear and well-established meaning (the definiens), and seek a word to refer to that content; it is a baptism. For this purpose, one might choose an ordinary word stripped of its ordinary meaning. By convention, physicists use the word charm to refer of a particular particle, the charm quark. The equivalence condition between the technical use of the word and its definition is fully satisfied.

In other cases, the word chosen to name the new phenomenon retains something of its ordinary meaning, and it is arguable that “my word fits the nature of the phenomenon better than yours ”. Since everyone has a preferred terminology, the relatively arbitrary nature of the stipulative neologism can lead to terminological inflation and a “war of words”, that can be overcome by invoking the primacy of the reality of things. Should we call such patterns of argumentation :

serial reasoning or subordinate argumentation?
linked reasoning or coordinated argumentation?
convergent reasoning or multiple argumentation?

If no agreement can be reached, the question can be settled radically, “You can even call it ‘Ivan Ivanovich’ as long as we all know what you mean.” (Jakobson 1971, p. 557).

3. Argumentation and definition

3.1 Argumentation constructing or evaluating a definition

Definitions are constructed argumentatively in reference to a set of rules, S. Argumentations constructing a definition.
These rules generate a set of specific argumentative lines that are exploited when a conflict of definitions arises, such as:

What exactly do you call a terrorist, a democracy, a spin doctor?

Persuasive definitions are definitions that are restructured to include or exclude an individual from their scope. They can be criticized as violating the non-circularity principle.

3.2 Argumentation based on a pre-existing definition

In this second case, the definition of a word is used as a store of arguments.

3.1.1 Definition used to categorize and name an individual

The argumentation naming an individual attaches this individual to a category name W, in reference to the definition of this category, S. Categorization and naming.

This is a mushroom

3.1.2 Definition used to enrich the description of an individual

In this form of argumentation, the speaker assigns to an individual any characteristic mentioned in the definition of its name.
If Syldavia is a democracy (category), and that “having fixed election dates” is a defining essential characteristic of democracy, then one might infer that there will be elections in Syldavia in the not too distant future, S. Argumentation based on a definition.

3.1.3 A discursive trick: Demanding a definition

The demand for a definition can be made with the intention of blocking the development of the opponent’s line of argument, S. Destruction of speech. The following exchange takes place in a discussion about different personalities competing for a scientific distinction:

S1:      — Doe has a lot of prestige.
S2:      — What do you call prestige?

This inevitably leads to a stasis of definition, a stalemate, in which many participants are not eager to participate.
The internal journal of a research institution objects to a traditional claim of laboratories:

“[Lack of technical staff] would lead to a lack of “optimal efficiency” in laboratories. First of all, how do we define the optimal efficiency of a laboratory?


[1] Wikipedia, Disappearing blond gene (10-09-21)
[1] Gastaud H. (1974) “Discussion”. In Morin E. & Piattelli-Palmarini M. (eds). (1974). L’Unité humaine. Paris: Le Seuil. P. 183. [The Unity of mankind)


 

Default Reasoning

DEFAULT REASONING

Researchers in artificial intelligence have developed the formal study of argumentation as defeasible reasoning in a logical, computational, and epistemological perspective.

1. Default reasoning

From the logical point of view, defeasible reasoning is studied within non-monotonic logic. Unlike conventional (“monotonic”) logic, non-monotonic logic admits the possibility that a conclusion that is not deducible from a set of premises {P1} can be deduced from  {P1} augmented of additional premises.
In terms of belief, the challenge is to formalize the basic idea that the provision of new information may lead to revision of the belief derived from a formerly limited set of data.

From an epistemological perspective, the theory of defeasible reasoning (Koons 2005) concerns beliefs that allow for exceptions: in general, birds fly; but penguins (Sphenisciformes, Spheniscidae) are birds and do not fly. Consequently, if the only thing one knows about Tweety is that Tweety is a bird, it is not possible, strictly speaking, to infer that Tweety can or cannot fly. Nevertheless, in the absence of any information suggesting that Tweety is a penguin (or some other flightless bird), the theory of revisable inference permits the conclusion “Tweety flies”. It validates exception-conditioned inferences:

Since A (Tweety is a bird), normally B (Tweety flies).

The premise does support the conclusion, but it may nonetheless be true and the conclusion false. A conclusion considered to be correct on the basis of the knowledge we have  now , may turn out to be false later, when further knowledge is gained.

The theory of defeasible reasoning also addresses complex questions such as the following. We know that:

(1) Birds fly
(2) Tweety is a bird
(3) Tweety does not fly
(4) Birds have highly developed wing muscles

In these conditions, can we deduce (5) from (1) – (4)?

(5) Tweety has highly developed wings muscles

The property of having highly developed wing muscles is related to having the ability to fly, which, according to the available information (3), is not true in the case of Tweety. The inferences from (1) and (4) to (5) is therefore invalidated. In other words, the conclusion “Tweety has highly developed wings muscles” is deducible not from “Tweety is a bird” but from “Tweety is a flying bird”.

A conclusion C asserted through defeasible reasoning can be refuted in two ways:
— On the one hand, by the existence of good arguments for a conclusion inconsistent with C (“rebutting defeater”, Koons 2005), that is to say, upon the existence of a strong counter-argumentation.
— On the other hand, upon the existence of good reasons to think that the transitional principles usually invoked in the argument do not apply in the case considered (“undercutting defeaters”, ibid), S. Refutation.

2. Representation of default reasoning

The reasoning (1) is represented as (2

(1) If Tweety is a bird,
in the absence of information suggesting that Tweety might be a penguin (etc.),
it is legitimate to conclude that Tweety flies.

(2)

Tweety is a bird: Tweety is not a penguin (etc.)

Tweety flies
ζ : η

θ

ζ: Prerequisite: we know that ζ
η: Rationale: η is compatible with available information
θ: Conclusion

The historical origins of the theory of revisable reasoning are to be sought in dialectical reasoning and the Topics of Aristotle. The restriction “in the absence of information” corresponds exactly to the “modal” component of Toulmin’s layout of argument; the basic intuitions and concepts are the same. Toulmin layout can be schematized as:

D (Data) : R (Rebuttal)

C (Claim)

D, Data: Prerequisites, we know that D.
R, Justification: The inference from D to C could be rebutted under the conditions R1… Rn; but we have no information leading us to believe that these rebuttal conditions are actually true.
C, Claim: So, the conclusion C can be accepted; we can assume that C.

Gabbay & Woods (2003) develop a study of practical reasoning that combine the insights of relevance theory and default reasoning theory.